Welcome to my research page.

I recently completed my Ph.D. in Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame, where I specialized in early modern European philosophy, with particular attention to the interplay between metaphysics, epistemology, and philosophy of mind. My dissertation, titled “Spinoza on Parallelism and the Ontology of Thought,” investigates the compatibility of Spinoza’s doctrine of parallelism with various challenging ideas. My broader research explores the metaphysical commitments of rationalist philosophers such as Descartes and Spinoza, focusing on how these commitments inform their accounts of the mind-body relationship, theories of representation, and conceptions of truth and falsity. Below are summaries of my current research projects.

Dissertation project: Spinoza on Parallelism and the Ontology of Thought

  • My dissertation investigates whether Spinoza can consistently uphold his doctrine of parallelism while acknowledging the existence of four distinct kinds of ideas that appear to challenge it. Parallelism, for Spinoza, asserts a one-to-one correspondence between each idea and its object, establishing an isomorphic structure between the mental and physical worlds. In my reading, this doctrine carries four implications: the number of modes under each attribute must be equal; every idea must correspond to and be true of its object; every idea must represent an external object; and each idea and its object are one and the same thing, although conceived under different attributes.

    However, Spinoza also recognizes four kinds of ideas that seem to undermine these commitments: ideas of ideas, which appear to multiply the number of modes under the attribute of thought; false ideas, which seem to violate the requirement that every idea be true of its object; beings of reason, which have no corresponding object outside the mind; and the idea of God, which raises questions about how a mode can be identical to substance.

    This project offers a systematic analysis of each of these apparent counterexamples. Drawing on Spinoza’s theory of distinctions and his account of representation, I argue that these ideas can be integrated into the framework of parallelism without sacrificing its core commitments. In doing so, the dissertation advances a more comprehensive understanding of Spinoza’s parallelism and sheds light on the character of Spinoza’s metaphysical system as shaped by the demands of parallelism.

  • Abstract: In the context of Spinoza’s monism, scholars have long struggled to explain why Spinoza considers the distinction between different attributes of God—the one and only substance—as a real distinction (E1p10s). In this paper, I argue that the difficulty arises from a general misunderstanding of Spinoza’s concept of real distinction. Despite their apparent similarity, Spinoza’s understanding of real distinction differs significantly from that of his predecessors, particularly Descartes. The difference is most evident in Spinoza’s interpretation of the criterion for real distinction, which he inherited from Descartes: “Two things are really distinct if one can be clearly conceived without the other, and vice versa.” Descartes understands this criterion to mean that two things are really distinct from each other if, even though the concept of one does not involve the concept of the other positively, it does involve the concept of the other negatively. On the other hand, Spinoza interprets the criterion as stating that one thing is really distinct from another if the concept of one does not include the concept of the other, whether positively or negatively. This seemingly subtle shift has significant implications at multiple levels. First, it breaks the traditional connection between real distinction and separability, resolving the apparent tension between Spinoza’s substance monism and the real distinction of attributes. Second, it also offers a coherent interpretation of Spinoza’s mode-identity thesis, showing how the mind and body, as modes conceived under different attributes, can be one and the same thing. Third, it demonstrates the compatibility of real distinction with numerical identity, directly challenging Leibniz’s Law, particularly the Indiscernibility of Identicals. Finally, it challenges the conventional understanding of distinction through negation and opposition, proposing instead that some distinctions are purely affirmative, opening up new ways of thinking about the nature of distinctions.

    This paper is committed to a forthcoming volume on Spinoza’s theory of attributes, edited by Antonio Salgado Borge and Karolina Hübner. A draft is available upon request.

  • Abstract: This paper addresses the tension in Spinoza’s philosophy between his doctrine of parallelism and the occurrence of errors in human cognition. While Spinoza posits that all ideas agree with their objects, implying truth, he also acknowledges human cognitive limitations and errors. The standard solution suggests separating parallelism from the criterion for true ideas, allowing for misrepresentation. Challenging this solution, I argue for the inseparability of Spinoza’s doctrine of parallelism from his criterion for true ideas. However, this does not imply the impossibility of error. Contrary to what commentators commonly assume, I argue that, for Spinoza, error consists not in misrepresentation but in the limited nature of individual finite minds, particularly the restricted scope of the objects they can represent. This limitation leads to the finite mind’s perpetual occupation of a partial perspective regarding the world.

    Draft is available upon request.

  • Abstract: This paper examines Spinoza’s puzzling treatment of beings of reason—objects of thought that correspond to nothing outside the intellect. Though Spinoza consistently uses this scholastic notion from the Short Treatise to the Ethics, his account raises three major interpretive challenges. First, unlike predecessors such as Suárez, Spinoza restricts the category to exclude self-contradictory and fictitious beings, prompting the Puzzle of Restricted Scope. Second, he classifies universals like genus and species as beings of reason, while also affirming the mind-independent existence of common properties, raising the Puzzle of Universality. Most fundamentally, the Puzzle of Parallelism questions how beings of reason can exist at all in a system that requires each idea to correspond to something outside the mind. I argue that all three puzzles can be resolved by understanding beings of reason as ideas of composite imaginative ideas. This interpretation accounts for their internal structure, distinguishes them from fictitious beings, and preserves their compatibility with Spinoza’s doctrine of parallelism. It also clarifies how Spinoza can maintain both the anti-realist status of universals and the reality of common properties, thus offering a unified solution to a longstanding tension in his metaphysical system.

    Draft is available upon request.

Descartes’s Theory of Representation and Its Scholastic Inheritance

  • This project investigates Descartes’s theory of representation by examining his engagement with a key scholastic distinction: the distinction between formal being (esse formale) and objective being (esse obiectivum). According to the scholastic view, one and the same thing can exist in multiple ways. The adverb “formally” (formaliter) and the corresponding expression “formal being” refer to the way something is in itself, independently of whether it is represented by an idea. In contrast, the adverb “objectively” (objective) and the expression “objective being” refer to the way something is thought about and is in the intellect.

    Descartes adopts this distinction and places it at the heart of his account of intentionality: for an idea to represent an object is for that very object to be **in the idea, and this special way of being constitutes its objective being. However, what is especially striking about Descartes is not simply that he adopts this distinction, but that he endorses a specific version of it—one that attributes a unique ontological status to objective being. In the Third Meditation, he asserts that objective being, “imperfect though it may be, is certainly not nothing, and so it cannot come from nothing” (AT VII 29, CSM II 41). This claim commits him to the view that whenever an idea represents something, that thing exists within the intellect in a meaningful and distinctive way, regardless of whether it exists outside the mind. A view that departs from a more deflationary account of objective being found in some of his contemporaries.

    By emphasizing the ontological import of objective being, Descartes’s theory of representation reveals itself to be more than an account of mental content: it has far-reaching implications for his broader metaphysical and epistemological framework.

  • This paper is currently under review. Abstract and draft are available upon request.

Spinoza on Collective Knowledge: Individuation, Interconnection, and Epistemic Community (in development)

  • This project aims to develop an account of collective knowledge grounded in Spinoza’s metaphysics. Drawing on his conception of individuals as finite modes of a single substance—God or Nature—it argues that Spinoza’s theory of individuation offers a framework for understanding knowledge not as an exclusively individual achievement, but as a process rooted in epistemic interdependence.

    The inquiry begins by examining how Spinoza’s metaphysical view dissolves rigid boundaries between individuals. As modes of one and the same substance, finite minds are ontologically interconnected, and their epistemic limitations—rooted in partial, inadequate ideas—can only be overcome through shared cognitive activity. On this basis, the project reconstructs a Spinozist model of collective knowledge, in which a community of minds functions as a unified epistemic subject capable of correcting error and arriving at more adequate understanding.